ðåôåðàòûðåôåðàòûðåôåðàòûðåôåðàòûðåôåðàòûðåôåðàòûðåôåðàòûðåôåðàòû

ðåôåðàòû, ñêà÷àòü ðåôåðàò, ñîâðåìåííûå ðåôåðàòû, ðåôåðàò íà òåìó, ðåôåðàòû áåñïëàòíî, áàíê ðåôåðàòîâ, ðåôåðàò êóëüòóðà, âèäû ðåôåðàòîâ, áåñïëàòíûå ðåôåðàòû, ýêîíîìè÷åñêèé ðåôåðàò

"ÑÀÌÛÉ ÁÎËÜØÎÉ ÁÀÍÊ ÐÅÔÅÐÀÒÎÂ"

Ïîðòàë Ðåôåðàòîâ

ðåôåðàòû
ðåôåðàòû
ðåôåðàòû

Ðåôåðàò: Adjective

Óíèâåðñèòåò Ðîññèéñêîé àêàäåìèè îáðàçîâàíèÿ

Ðåôåðàò

ïî òåîðåòè÷åñêîé ãðàììàòèêå

íà òåìó: “Adjective”

Ôàêóëüòåò

èíîñòðàííûõ ÿçûêîâ

311 ãðóïïà

Ìîñêâà, 2001

The adjective expresses the categorial semantics of property of a substance. It

means that each adjective used in tile text presupposes relation to some noun

the property of whose referent it denotes, such as its material, colour,

dimensions, position, state, and other characteristics both per­manent and

temporary. It follows from this that, unlike nouns, adjectives do not possess a

full nominative value. Indeed, words like long, hospitable, fragrant

cannot effect any self-dependent nominations; as units of informative sequences

they exist only in collocations showing what is long, who is hospitable, what

is fragrant.

The semantically bound character of the adjective is emphasized in English by

the use of the prop-substitute one in the absence of the notional

head-noun of the phrase. E.g.:

I don't want a yellow balloon, let me have the green one over there.

On the other hand, if the adjective is placed in a nominatively self-dependent

position, this leads to its substantivi­zation. E.g.: Outside it was a

beautiful day, and the sun tinged the snow with red. Cf.: The sun

tinged the snow with the red colour.

Adjectives are distinguished by a specific combinability with nouns, which

they modify, if not accompanied by ad­juncts, usually in pre-position, and

occasionally in post­position; by a combinability with link-verbs, both

functional and notional; by a combinability with modifying adverbs.

In the sentence the adjective performs the functions of an attribute and a

predicative. Of the two, the more specific function of the adjective is

that of an attribute, since the function of a predicative can be performed by

the noun as well. There is, though, a profound difference between the

predicative uses of the adjective and the noun which is de­termined by their

native categorial features. Namely, the predicative adjective expresses some

attributive property of its noun-referent, whereas the predicative noun

expresses various substantival characteristics of its referent, such as its

identification or classification of different types. This can be shown on

examples analysed by definitional and transfor­mational procedures. Cf.:

You talk to people as if they were a group. —> You talk to people as

if they formed a group. Quite obviously, he was a friend. —>

His behaviour was like that of a friend.

Cf., as against the above:

I will be silent as a grave. —> I will be like a silent grave

. Walker felt healthy. —> Walker felt a healthy man. It was

sensational. —> That fact was a sensational fact.

When used as predicatives or post-positional attributes, a considerable number

of adjectives, in addition to the gen­eral combinability characteristics of the

whole class, are distinguished by a complementive combinability with nouns. The

complement-expansions of adjectives are effected by means of prepositions.

E.g. fond of, jealous of, curious of, suspicious of; angry with, sick with,

serious about, certain about, happy about; grateful to, thankful to, etc.

Many such adjectival collocations render essentially verbal meanings and some

of them have direct or indirect parallels among verbs. Cf.: be fond of

—love, like; be envious of — envy; be angry with — resent;

be mad for, about - covet; be thank­ful to — thank.

Alongside of other complementive relations expressed with the help of

prepositions and corresponding to direct and prep­ositional object-relations of

verbs, some of these adjectives may render relations of addressee. Cf.:

grateful to, indebted to, partial to, useful for.

To the derivational features of adjectives belong a number of suffixes and

prefixes of which the most important are:

-ful (hopeful), -less (flawless),-ish (bluish, -ous

(famous), -ive (decorative), -ic (basic); un-

(unprecedented), in- (inac­curate), pre- (premature).

Among the adjectival affixes should also be named the prefix a-,

constitutive for the stative sub-­class which is to be discussed below.

As for the variable (demutative) morphological features, the English

adjective, having lost in the course of the history of English all its forms

of grammatical agreement with the noun, is distinguished only by the hybrid

category of com­parison.

All the adjectives are traditionally divided into two large subclasses:

qualitative and relative.

Relative adjectives express such properties of a substance as are

determined by the direct relation of the substance to some other substance.

E.g.: wood — a wooden hut; mathemat­ics — mathematical

precision; history — a historical event;

table — tabular presentation; colour — coloured postcards;

surgery — surgical treatment; the Middle Ages — mediaeval rites.

The nature of this "relationship" in adjectives is best revealed by definitional

correlations. Cf.: a wooden hut — a hut made of wood; a

historical event — an event referring to a certain period of history;

surgical treatment — treat­ment consisting in the implementation of surgery;

etc.

Qualitative adjectives, as different from relative ones, denote various

qualities of substances which admit of a quantitative estimation, i.e. of

establishing their correla­tive quantitative measure. The measure of a quality

can be estimated as high or low, adequate or inadequate, sufficient or

insufficient, optimal or excessive. Cf.: an awkward situa­tion

— a very awkward situation; a difficult task — too

dif­ficult a task; an enthusiastic reception — rather an

enthu­siastic reception; a hearty welcome — not a very hearty

wel­come; etc.

In this connection, the ability of an adjective to form degrees of comparison is

usually taken as a formal sign of its qualitative character, in opposition to a

relative adjective which is understood as incapable of forming degrees of

com­parison by definition. Cf.: a pretty girl --a prettier

girl; a quick look — a quicker look; a hearty welcome —

the heart­iest of welcomes; a bombastic speech — the most

bombastic speech.

However, in actual speech the described principle of dis­tinction is not at

all strictly observed, which is noted in the very grammar treatises putting

it forward. Two typical cases of contradiction should be pointed out here.

In the first place, substances can possess such qualities as are incompatible

with the idea of degrees of comparison. Accordingly, adjectives denoting these

qualities, while be­longing to the qualitative subclass, are in the ordinary

use incapable of forming degrees of comparison. Here refer ad­jectives like

extinct, immobile, deaf, final, fixed, etc.

In the second place, many adjectives considered under the heading of relative

still can form degrees of comparison, thereby, as it were, transforming the

denoted relative prop­erty of a substance into such as can be graded

quantitative­ly. Cf.: a mediaeval approach—rather a

mediaeval ap­proach — a far more mediaeval approach; of a

military de­sign — of a less military design — of a more

military design;

a grammatical topic ~ a purely grammatical topic — the most

grammatical of the suggested topics.

In order to overcome the demonstrated lack of rigour in the definitions in

question, we may introduce an additional linguistic distinction which is more

adaptable to the chances of usage. The suggested distinction is based on the

evalua­tive function of adjectives. According as they actually give some

qualitative evaluation to the substance referent or only point out its

corresponding native property, all the adjective functions may be

grammatically divided into "evaluative" and "specificative". In particular,

one and the same adjec­tive, irrespective of its being basically (i.e. in the

sense of the fundamental semantic property of its root constituent)

"relative" or "qualitative", can be used either in the evalua­tive function

or in the specificative function.

For instance, the adjective good is basically qualitative. On the other

hand, when employed as a grading term in teach­ing, i.e. a term forming part of

the marking scale together with the grading terms bad, satisfactory,

excellent, it acquires the said specificative value; in other words, it

becomes a spe­cificative, not an evaluative unit in the grammatical sense

(though, dialectically, it does signify in this case a lexical evaluation of the

pupil's progress). Conversely, the adjective wooden is basically relative, but

when used in the broader meaning "expressionless" or "awkward" it acquires an

eval­uative force and, consequently, can presuppose a greater or lesser degree

("amount") of the denoted properly in the corresponding referent. E.g.:

Bundle found herself looking into the expressionless, wooden face of

Superintendent Battle (A. Christie). The su­perintendent was sitting behind a

table and looking more wooden than ever.

The degrees of comparison are essentially evaluative for­mulas, therefore any

adjective used in a higher comparison degree (comparative, superlative) is

thereby made into an evaluative adjective, if only for the nonce (see the

examples above).

Thus, the introduced distinction between the evaluative and specificative

uses of adjectives, in the long run, empha­sizes the fact that the

morphological category of comparison (comparison degrees) is potentially

represented in the whole class of adjectives and is constitutive for it.

Among the words signifying properties of a nounal referent there is a lexemic

set which claims to be recognized as a separate part of speech, i.e. as a class

of words different from the adjectives in its class-forming features. These are

words built up by the prefix a- and denoting different states, mostly

of temporary duration. Here belong lexemes like afraid, agog, adrift,

ablaze. In traditional grammar these words were generally considered under

the heading of "pre­dicative adjectives" (some of them also under the heading

of adverbs), since their most typical position in the sentence is that of a

predicative and they are but occasionally used as pre-positional attributes to

nouns.

Notional words signifying states and specifically used as predicatives were

first identified as a separate part of speech in the Russian language by L. V.

Shcherba and V. V. Vinogradov. The two scholars called the newly iden­tified

part of speech the "category of state" (and, correspond­ingly, separate words

making up this category, "words of the category of state"). Here belong the

Russian words mostly ending in -o, but also having other suffixes:

òåïëî, çÿáêî, îäèíîêî, ðàäîñòíî, æàëü, ëåíü, etc. Traditionally the Russian

words of the category of state were considered as constituents of (he class of

adverbs, and they are still considered as such by many Russian schiolars.

On the analogy of the Russian "category of state", the English qualifying a-

words of the corresponding meanings were subjected to a lexico-grammatical

analysis and given the part-of-speech heading "category of slate". This

analysis was first conducted by B. A. llyish and later continued by other

linguists. The term "words of the category of state", being rather cumbersome

from the technical point of view, was later changed into "stative words", or

"statives".

The part-of-speech interpretation of the statives is not shared by all

linguists working in the domain of English, and has found both its proponents

and opponents.

Probably the most consistent and explicit exposition of the part-of-speech

interpretation of statives has been given by B. S. Khaimovich and B. I.

Rogovskaya. Their theses supporting the view in question can be summarized as

follows.

First, the statives, called by the quoted authors "adlinks" (by virtue of their

connection with link-verbs and on the analogy of the term "adverbs"), are

allegedly opposed to adjectives on a purely semantic basis, since adjectives

denote "qualities", and statives-adlinks denote "states". Second, as different

from adjectives, statives-adlinks are characterized by the specific prefix

a-. Third, they allegedly do not possess the category of the degrees of

comparison. Fourth, the combinability of statives-adlinks is different from

that of adjectives in so far as they are not used in the pre-positional

attributive function, i.e. are characterized by the absence of the right-hand

combinability with nouns.

The advanced reasons, presupposing many-sided categorial estimation of

statives, are undoubtedly serious and worthy of note. Still, a closer

consideration of the properties of the analysed lexemic set cannot but show

that, on the whole, the said reasons are hardly instrumental in proving the

main idea, i.e. in establishing the English stative as a separate part of

speech. The re-consideration of the stative on the basis of comparison with

the classical adjective inevitably discloses (lie fundamental relationship

between the two, — such relationship as should be interpreted in no other

terms than identity on the part-of-speech level, though, naturally, providing

for their distinct differentiation on the subclass level.

The first scholar who undertook this kind of re-consider­ation of the lexemic

status of English statives was L. S. Barkhudarov, and in our estimation of

them we essentially fol­low his principles, pointing out some additional

criteria of argument.

First, considering the basic meaning expressed by the stative, we formulate

it as "stative property", i.e. a kind of property of a nounal referent. As we

already know, the adjective as a whole signifies not "quality" in the narrow

sense, but "property", which is categorially divided into "substantive

quality as such" and "substantive relation". In this respect, statives do not

fundamentally differ from classical adjectives. Moreover, common adjectives

and partici­ples in adjective-type functions can express the same, or, more

specifically, typologically the same properties (or "qual­ities" in a broader

sense) as are expressed by statives.

Indeed, the main meaning types conveyed by statives are:

the psychic state of a person (afraid, ashamed, aware); the physical

state of a person (astir, afoot); the physical state of an object (

afire, ablaze, aglow); the state of an object in space (askew, awry,

aslant). Meanings of the same order are rendered by pre-positional

adjectives. Cf.:

the living predecessor — the predecessor alive; eager

curi­osity — curiosity agog; the burning house — the house

afire; a floating raft — a raft afloat; a half-open door — a

door adjar; slanting ropes — ropes aslant; a

vigilant man — a man awake;

similar cases — cases alike; an excited crowd — a crowd astir.

It goes without saying that many other adjectives and participles convey the

meanings of various states irrespective of their analogy with statives. Cf

. such words of the order of psychic state as despondent, curious, happy,

joyful; such words of the order of human physical state as sound,

refreshed, healthy, hungry; such words of the order of activity state as

busy, functioning, active, employed, etc.

Second, turning to the combinability characteristics of statives, we see that,

though differing from those of the com­mon adjectives in one point negatively,

they basically coin­cide with them in the other points. As a matter of fact,

sta­tives are not used in attributive pre-position. but, like ad­jectives, they

are distinguished by the left-hand categorial combinability both with nouns and

link-verbs. Cf.:

The household was nil astir.——The household was all excited — It was

strange to see (the household active at this hour of the day.— It was

strange to see the household active at this hour of the day.

Third, analysing the functions of the stative correspond­ing to its

combinability patterns, we see that essentially they do not differ from the

functions of the common ad­jective. Namely, the two basic functions of the

stative are the predicative and the attribute. The similarity of functions

leads to the possibility of the use of a stative and a common adjective in a

homogeneous group. E.g.: Launches and barges moored to the dock were

ablaze and loud with wild sound.

True, the predominant function of the stative, as differ­ent from the common

adjective, is that of the predicative. But then, the important structural and

functional peculiari­ties of statives uniting them in a distinctly separate

set of lexemes cannot be disputed. What is disputed is the status of this set

in relation to the notional parts of speech, not its existence or

identification as such.

Fourth, from our point of view, it would not be quite consistent with the

actual lingual data to place the stative strictly out of the category of

comparison. As we have shown above, the category of comparison is connected

with the func­tional division of adjectives into evaluative and

specificative, Like common adjectives, statives are subject to this flexible

division, and so in principle they are included into the expression of the

quantitative estimation of the corre­sponding properties conveyed by them.

True, statives do not take the synthetical forms of the degrees of

comparison, but they are capable of expressing comparison analytically, in

cases where it is to be expressed.

Cf.: Of us all, Jack was the one most aware of the delicate

situation in which we found ourselves. I saw that the adjust­ing lever stood

far more askew than was allowed by the di­rections.

Fifth, quantitative considerations, though being a sub­sidiary factor of

reasoning, tend to support the conjoint part-of-speech interpretation of

statives and common adjectives. Indeed, the total number of statives does not

exceed several dozen (a couple of dozen basic, "stable" units and, probably,

thrice as many "unstable" words of the nature of coinages for the nonce).

This num­ber is negligible in comparison with the number of words of the

otherwise identified notional parts of speech, each of them counting

thousands of units. Why, then, an honour of the part-of-speech status to be

granted to a small group of words not differing in their fundamental lexico-

grammatical features from one of the established large word-classes?

As for the set-forming prefix a-, it hardly deserves a se­rious

consideration as a formal basis of the part-of-speech identification of

statives simply because formal features cannot be taken in isolation from

functional features. More­over, as is known, there are words of property not

distinguished by this prefix, which display essential functional

character­istics inherent in the stative set. In particular, here belong such

adjectives as ill, well, glad, sorry, worth (while), subject (to), due

(to), underway, and some others. On the other hand, among the basic

statives we find such as can hardly be ana­lysed into a genuine combination of

the type "prefix + root", because their morphemic parts have become fused into

one indivisible unit in the course of language history, e.g. aware, afraid,

aloof.

Thus, the undertaken semantic and functional analysis shows that statives,

though forming a unified set of words, do not constitute a separate lexemic

class existing in lan­guage on exactly the same footing as the noun, the

verb, the adjective, the adverb; rather it should be looked upon as a

subclass within the general class of adjectives. It is essentially an

adjectival subclass, because, due to their pe­culiar features, statives are

not directly opposed to the no­tional parts of speech taken together, but are

quite particu­larly opposed to the rest of adjectives. It means that the

gen­eral subcategorization of the class of adjectives should be effected on

the two levels: on the upper level the class will be divided into the

subclass of stative adjectives and com­mon adjectives; on the lower level the

common adjectives fall into qualitative and relative, which division has been

discussed in the foregoing paragraph.

As we see, our final conclusion about the lexico-grammatical nature of

statives appears to have returned them into the lexemic domain in which they

were placed by traditional grammar and from which they were alienated in the

course of subsequent linguistic investigations. A question then arises,

whether these investigations, as well as the discussions accompanying them,

have served any rational purpose at all.

The answer to this question, though, can only be given in the energetic

affirmative. Indeed, all the detailed studies of statives undertaken by quite

a few scholars, all the dis­cussions concerning their systemic location and

other related matters have produced very useful results, both theoretical and

practical.

The traditional view of the stative was not supported by any special

analysis, it was formed on the grounds of mere surface analogies and outer

correlations. The later study of statives resulted in the exposition of their

inner properties, in the discovery of their historical productivity as a

sub­class, in their systemic description on the lines of competent inter-

class and inter-level comparisons. And it is due to the undertaken

investigations (which certainly will be continued) that we are now in a

position, though having rejected the fundamental separation of the stative

from the adjective, to name the subclass of statives as one of the peculiar,

idio­matic lexemic features of Modern English.

As is widely known, adjectives display the ability to be easily

substantivized by conversion, i.e. by zero-deriv­ation. Among the noun-

converted adjectives we find both old units, well-established in the system

of lexicon, and also new ones, whose adjectival etymology conveys to the

lexeme the vivid colouring of a new coinage.

For instance, the words a relative or a white or a dear

bear an unquestionable mark of established tradition, while such a noun as a

sensitive used in the following sentence fea­tures a distinct flavour of

purposeful conversion: He was a regional man, a man who wrote about

sensitives who live away from the places where things happen.

Compare this with the noun a high in the following exam­ple: The weather

report promises a new high in heat and humidity.

From the purely categorial point of view, however, there is no difference

between the adjectives cited in the examples and the ones given in the

foregoing enumeration, since both groups equally express constitutive

categories of the noun, i.e. the number, the case, the gender, the article

determina­tion, and they likewise equally perform normal nounal func­tions.

On the other hand, among the substantivized adjectives there is a set

characterized by hybrid lexico-grammatical features, as in the following

examples:

The new bill concerning the wage-freeze introduced by the Labour Government

cannot satisfy either the poor, or the rich (Radio Broadcast).

A monster. The word conveyed the ultimate in infamy and debasement

inconceivable to one not native to the times (J. Vance). The train, indulging

all his English nostalgia for the plushy and the genteel, seemed to him

a deceit (M. Bradbury).

The mixed categorial nature of the exemplified words is evident from their

incomplete presentation of the part-of speech characteristics of either nouns

or adjectives. Like nouns, the words are used in the article form; like

nouns, they express the category of number (in a relational way); but their

article and number forms are rigid, being no sub­ject to the regular

structural change inherent in the normal expression of these categories.

Moreover, being categorially unchangeable, the words convey the mixed

adjectival-nounal semantics of property.

The adjectival-nounal words in question are very specific. They are

distinguished by a high productivity and, like sta­tives, are idiomatically

characteristic of Modern English.

On the analogy of verbids these words might be called "adjectivids", since

they are rather nounal forms of adjectives than nouns as such.

The adjectivids fall into two main grammatical sub­groups, namely, the subgroup

pluralia tantum {the English, the rich, the unemployed, the uninitiated

, etc.), and the sub­group singularia tantum (the invisible, the

abstract, the tangible, etc.). Semantically, the words of the first

subgroup express sets of people (personal multitudes), while the words of the

second group express abstract ideas of various types and connotations.

The category of adjectival comparison expresses the quantitative

characteristic of the quality of a nounal referent, i.e. it gives a relative

evaluation of the quantity of a quality. The purely relative nature of the

categorial semantics of comparison is reflected in its name.

The category is constituted by the opposition of the three forms known under the

heading of degrees of comparison: the basic form (positive degree),

having no features of corn" parison; the comparative degree form,

having the feature of restricted .superiority (which limits the comparison to

two elements only); the superlative degree form, having the fea­ture of

unrestricted superiority.

It should be noted that the meaning of unrestricted su­periority is in-built in

the superlative degree as such, though in practice this form is used in

collocations imposing certain restrictions on the effected comparison; thus,

the form in question may be used to signify restricted superiority, name­ly, in

cases where a limited number of referents are com­pared. Cf.: Johnny

was the strongest boy in the com­pany.

As is evident from the example, superiority restriction is shown here not by

the native meaning of the superlative, but by the particular contextual

construction of comparison where the physical strength of one boy is

estimated in rela­tion to that of his companions.

Some linguists approach the number of the degrees of comparison as

problematic on the grounds that the basic form of the adjective does not

express any comparison by itself and therefore should be excluded from the

category. This exclusion would reduce the category to two members only, i.e.

the comparative and superlative degrees.

However, the oppositional interpretation of grammatical categories underlying

our considerations does not admit of such an exclusion; on the contrary, the

non-expression of superiority by the basic form is understood in the

oppositional presentation of comparison as a pre-requisite for the

ex­pression of the category as such. In this expression of the category the

basic form is the unmarked member, not distin­guished by any comparison

suffix or comparison auxiliary, while the superiority forms (i.e. the

comparative and super­lative) are the marked members, distinguished by the

com­parison suffixes or comparison auxiliaries.

That the basic form as the positive degree of comparison does express this

categorial idea, being included in one and the same calegorial series with the

superiority degrees, is clearly shown by its actual uses in comparative

syntactic constructions of equality, as well as comparative syntactic

constructions of negated equality. Cf.: The remark was as bitter

as could be. The Rockies are not so high as the Caucasus.

These constructions are directly correlative with comparat­ive constructions of

inequality built around the comparative and superlative degree forms. Cf

.: That was the bitterest remark I have ever heard from the man. The

Caucasus is higher than the Rockies.

Thus, both formally and semantically, the oppositional basis of the category

of comparison displays a binary nature. In terms of the three degrees of

comparison, on the upper level of presentation the superiority degrees as the

marked member of the opposition are contrasted against the positive degree as

its unmarked member. The superiority degrees, in their turn, form the

opposition of the lower level of pres­entation, where the comparative degree

features the func­tionally weak member, and the superlative degree,

re­spectively, the strong member. The whole of the double op­positional

unity, considered from the semantic angle, con­stitutes a gradual ternary

opposition.

The synthetical forms of comparison in -er and -(e)st coexist

with the analytical forms of comparison effected by the auxiliaries more

and most. The analytical forms of comparison perform a double function.

On the one hand, they are used with the evaluative adjectives that, due to

their phonemic structure (two-syllable words with the stress on the first

syllable ending in other grapho-phonemic complexes than -er, -y, -le, -ow

or words of more than two-syllable composition) cannot normally take the

synthetical forms of comparison. In this respect, the analytical com­parison

forms are in categorial complementary distribution with the synthetical

comparison forms. On the other hand, the analytical forms of comparison, as

different from the synthetical forms, are used to express emphasis, thus

com­plementing the synthetical forms in the sphere of this im­portant stylistic

connotation. Cf.: The audience became more and more noisy

, and soon the speaker's words were drowned in the general hum of voices.

The structure of the analytical degrees of comparison is meaningfully overt;

these forms are devoid of the feature of "semantic idiomatism" characteristic

of some other categor­ial analytical forms, such as, for instance, the forms

of the verbal perfect. For this reason the analytical degrees of com­parison

invite some linguists to call in question their claim to a categorial status

in English grammar.

In particular, scholars point out the following two fac­tors in support of the

view that the combinations of more/most with the basic form of the

adjective are not the analytical expressions of the morphological category of

comparison, but free syntactic constructions: first, the more/most

-com­binations are semantically analogous to combinations of less/least

with the adjective which, in the general opinion, are syntactic combinations of

notional words; second, the most-combination, unlike the synthetic

superlative, can take the indefinite article, expressing not the superlative,

but the elative meaning (i.e. a high, not the highest degree of the respective

quality).

The reasons advanced, though claiming to be based on an analysis of actual

lingual data, can hardly be called con­vincing as regards their immediate

negative purpose.

Let us first consider the use of the most-combillation with the

indefinite article.

This combination is a common means of expressing elative evaluations of

substance properties. The function of the elative most-construction in

distinction to the function of the superlative most-'construction will

be seen from the fol­lowing examples:

The speaker launched a most significant personal attack on the Prime

Minister. The most significant of the arguments in a dispute is not

necessarily the most spectacular one.

While the phrase "a most significant (personal) attack" in the first of the two

examples gives the idea of rather a high degree of the quality expressed

irrespective of any directly introduced or implied comparison with other

attacks on the Prime Minister, the phrase "the most significant of the

ar­guments" expresses exactly the superlative degree of the quality in relation

to the immediately introduced com­parison with all the rest of the arguments in

a dispute; the same holds true of the phrase "the most spectacular one". It is

this exclusion of the outwardly superlative ad­jective from a comparison that

makes it into a simple elative, with its most-constituent turned from

the superlative aux­iliary into a kind of a lexical intensifier.

The definite article with the elative most-construction is also

possible, if leaving the elative function less distinctly recognizable (in oral

speech the elative most is commonly left unstressed, the absence of

stress serving as a negative mark of the elative). Cf.: I found myself

in the most awkward situation, for I couldn't give a satisfactory

answer to any question asked by the visitors.

Now, the synthetical superlative degree, as is known, can be used in the

elative function as well, the distinguishing feature of the latter being its

exclusion from a comparison.

Cf.:

Unfortunately, our cooperation with Danny proved the worst experience

for both of us. No doubt Mr. Snider will show you his collection of minerals

with the greatest pleas­ure.

And this fact gives us a clue for understanding the ex­pressive nature of the

elative superlative as such — the na­ture that provides it with a permanent

grammatico-stylistic status in the language. Indeed, the expressive

peculiarity of the form consists exactly in the immediate combination of the

two features which outwardly contradict each other:

the categorial form of the superlative on the one hand, and the absence of a

comparison on the other.

That the categorial form of the superlative (i.e. the su­perlative with its

general functional specification) is essen­tial also for the expression of the

elative semantics can, how­ever paradoxical it might appear, be very well

illustrated by the elative use of the comparative degree. Indeed, the

com­parative combination featuring the dative comparative de­gree is

constructed in such a way as to place it in the func­tional position of

unrestricted superiority, i.e. in the po­sition specifically characteristic of

the superlative. E.g.:

Nothing gives me greater pleasure than to greet you as our guest of

honour. There is nothing more refreshing than a good swim.

The parallelism of functions between the two forms of comparison (the

comparative degree and the superlative de­gree) in such and like examples is

unquestionable.

As we see, the elative superlative, though it is not the regular superlative in

the grammatical sense, is still a kind of a specific, grammatically featured

construction. This grammatical specification distinguishes it from common

elative constructions which may be generally defined as syn­tactic combinations

of an intensely high estimation. E.g.:

an extremely important amendment; a matter of exceeding urgency;

quite an unparalleled beauty; etc.

Thus, from a grammatical point of view, the elative su­perlative, though

semantically it is "elevated", is nothing else but a degraded superlative,

and its distinct featuring mark with the analytical superlative degree is the

indefinite article: the two forms of the superlative of different function­al

purposes receive the two different marks (if not quite rig­orously separated

in actual uses) by the article determina­tion treatment.

It follows from the above that the possibility of the most-combination

to be used with the indefinite article cannot in any way be demonstrative of

its non-grammatical character, since the functions of the two superlative

combinations in question, the elative superlative and the genuine superla­tive,

are different.

Moreover, the use of the indefinite article with the syn­thetical superlative in

the degraded, dative function is not altogether impossible, though somehow such

a possibility is bluntly denied by certain grammatical manuals. Cf.: He

made a last lame effort to delay the experiment; but Basil was

impervious to suggestion.

But there is one more possibility to formally differentiate the direct and

dative functions of the synthetical superlative, namely, by using the zero

article with the superlative. This latter possibility is noted in some grammar

books (Ganshina, Vasilevskaya, 85). Cf.: Suddenly I was seized with a

sen­sation of deepest regret.

However, the general tendency of expressing the super­lative dative meaning is

by using the analytical form. Inci­dentally, in the Russian language the

tendency of usage is reverse: it is the synthetical form of the Russian

superlative that is preferred in rendering the dative function. Cf.:

ñëóøàëè ñ æèâåéøèì èíòåðåñîì; ïîâòîðÿëàñü ñêó÷íåéøàÿ èñòîðèÿ;

ïîïàë â ãëóïåéøåå ïîëîæåíèå è ò.ä.

Let us examine now the combinations of less/least with the basic form of

the adjective.

As is well known, the general view of these combinations definitely excludes

them from any connection with categorial analytical forms. Strangely enough,

this rejectionist view of the "negative degrees of comparison" is even taken to

sup­port, not to reject the morphological interpretation of the more/most

-combinations.

The corresponding argument in favour of the rejectionist interpretation consists

in pointing out the functional parallel­ism existing between the synthetical

degrees of comparison and the more/most-combinations accompanied by

their com­plementary distribution, if not rigorously pronounced (the different

choice of the forms by different syllabo-phonetical forms of adjectives). The

less/least-combinations, according to this view, are absolutely incompatible

with the synthetical degrees of comparison, since they express not only

different, but opposite meanings.

Now, it does not require a profound analysis to see that, from the

grammatical point of view, the formula "opposite meaning" amounts to

ascertaining the categorial equality of the forms compared. Indeed, if two

forms express the op­posite meanings, then they can only belong to units of

the same general order. And we cannot but agree with B. A. Ilyish's thesis

that "there seems to be no sufficient reason for treating the two sets of

phrases in different ways, saying that 'more difficult' is an analytical

form, while 'less difficult' is not" [Ilyish, 60]. True, the cited author

takes this fact rather as demonstration that both types of constructions

should equally be excluded from the domain of analytical forms, but the

problem of the categorial status of the more/most-combinations has been

analysed above.

Thus, the less/least-combinations, similar to the more/most

-combinations, constitute specific forms of comparison, which may be called

forms of "reverse comparison". The two types of forms cannot be syntagmatically

combined in one and the same form of the word, which shows the unity of the

category of comparison. The whole category includes not three, but five

different forms, making up the two ser­ies — respectively, direct and reverse.

Of these, the reverse series of comparison (the reverse superiority degrees) is

of far lesser importance than the direct one, which evidently can be explained

by semantic reasons. As a matter of fact, it is more natural to follow the

direct model of comparison based on the principle of addition of qualitative

quantities than on the reverse model of comparison based on the prin­ciple of

subtraction of qualitative quantities, since subtrac­tion in general is a far

more abstract process of mental ac­tivity than addition. And, probably, exactly

for the same reason the reverse comparatives and superlatives are rivalled in

speech by the corresponding negative syntactic construc­tions.

Having considered the characteristics of the category of comparison, we can

see more clearly the relation to this category of some usually non-comparable

evaluative ad­jectives.

Outside the immediate comparative grammatical change of the adjective stand such

evaluative adjectives as contain certain comparative sememic elements in their

semantic structures. In particular, as we have mentioned above, here belong

adjectives that are themselves grading marks of eval­uation. Another group of

evaluative non-comparables is formed by adjectives of indefinitely moderated

quality, or, tentatively, "moderating qualifiers", such as whitish, tepid,

half-ironical, semi-detached, etc. But the most peculiar lexemic group of

non-comparables is made up by adjectives expressing the highest degree of a

respective quality, which words can tentatively be called "adjectives of

extreme quali­ty", or "extreme qualifiers", or simply "extremals".

The inherent superlative semantics of extremals is em­phasized by the definite

article normally introducing their nounal combinations, exactly similar to the

definite article used with regular collocations of the superlative degree.

Cf.: The ultimate outcome of the talks was encouraging. The

final decision has not yet been made public.

On the other hand, due to the tendency of colloquial speech to contrastive

variation, such extreme qualifiers can some­times be modified by intensifying

elements. Thus, "the final decision" becomes "a very final decision"; "the

ultimate rejection" turns into "rather an ultimate rejection"; "the crucial

role" is made into "quite a crucial role", etc.

As a result of this kind of modification, the highest grade evalu­ative force

of these words is not strengthened, but, on the con­trary, weakened; the

outwardly extreme qualifiers become degraded extreme qualifiers, even in this

status similar to the regular categorial superlatives degraded in their

elative use.

LITERATURE

1. Ilyish B. “The structure of modern English”, M, 1971

2. Bloch M. “The course in the English grammar”, M, 1983

ðåôåðàòû
ÐÅÔÅÐÀÒÛ © 2010